In his book, La bienveillance dans les relations internationales. Un essai politique (CNRS Editions, January 2022), Frédéric Ramel sets out to examine and analyse international relations through the lens of benevolence. A professor of political science and researcher at the Centre for International Studies, Ramel opposes the cynical commentators who consider the notion of benevolence naive, and provides an alternative and more sensitive perspective on past and present international relations and could inspire those of tomorrow. Interview.
Frédéric Ramel: it’s important to make a distinction between benevolence as a disposition and benevolence as an action. All human beings can recognise behaviour based on benevolence – not causing harm to others (negative benevolence), helping those who are vulnerable, and/or taking reasonable steps to promote the good (positive benevolence). As spectators, we can all evaluate and admire the actions of someone like Denis Mukwege, the gynaecologist who ‘repairs’ women who are victims of rape in conflicts in Africa, or someone like Leymah Gbowee, the Christian leader who promotes non-violence and advocates for the inclusion of women in the peace process is in Liberia. However, taking action (either planned or spontaneous) is not automatic.
F.R.: Benevolence is not the prerogative of a select few. The first actors who come to mind are diplomats, who take into account this disposition or even trigger it in immediate response to suffering endured by their counterparts and fellow citizens following terrorist attacks or natural disasters. I also refer to the resonance these diplomats may experience in their practices by cultivating calm and silence, which might be described as an acoustic reading (1)An acoustic reading refers to the role of listening, silence, and resonance in the everyday work of diplomats who produce sound, modulate their voices, organise concerts as instruments of representation and mediation. See Damien Mahiet, Rebekah Ahrendt, Frédéric Ramel. “Diplomacy: Audible and Resonant,” Diplomatica. A Journal of Diplomacy and Society, Dec. 2021of their profession that help to make diplomatic relationships more solid, whether in negotiation situations or during commemorations.
But I also broaden this exploration of benevolence to other actors: intergovernmental organisations who contribute to cultivating social multilateralism in a spirit of solidarity (improving the living conditions for individuals, such as the International Labour Organisation for example); paradiplomacy cultivates by cities based on cooperation in terms of urban planning, transport, waste management, and which encourages improvements in well-being at the local level(2)« Interview with Rodrigo Tavares over Paradiplomatic Trend », IR Insider, 17 septembre 2018. ; and NGOs who promote assistance for the most vulnerable. Ordinary individuals are another important link in this chain and can also mobilise actions of benevolence to assist migrants (hospitality), change their forms of consumerism through new ways of managing shared spaces, or the preference for local producers (sobriety).
This exploration encourages us to recognise benevolence not as a substitute for power – still less as the foundation of international politics, that would be totally utopian – but as a kind of glue, a cement that primarily serves to encourage civility. As Pierre Hassner rightly emphasised in La revanche des passions, ‘if we do not, to varying degrees, have some sense of fraternity, a world that is based exclusively on interests or one exclusively based on identities cannot function’. This recognition forces us to concretise our understanding of the conditions that help to liberate benevolence. In this respect, representatives of the English school such as Andrew Linklater, following on from Norbert Elias, have already contributed to the demonstration of the links between self-restraint and interdependence effects(3)Andrew Linklater, The Problem of Harm in World Politics, Cambridge University Press, 2011. Andrew Linklater, Violence and Civilization in the Western States-Systems, Cambridge University Press, 2016..
F.R.: Negative benevolence consists of not hurting others. It goes hand in hand with the principle of doing no harm. In international law, the basis of the due diligence principle, which promotes the idea of refraining from harm even before an action is undertaken, is based on the principle of benevolence itself because it activates concentrated attention to otherness. This negative benevolence must not be confused with the darker sides of benevolence which I explore in my book. Indeed, I do not rule out the potential negative side effects of an action conducted in the name of benevolence, of which the effects may come into tension with the basis of its very nature, what Ricoeur called the ‘affective substance’ of respect(4)Paul Ricœur, « Sympathie et respect : phénoménologie et éthique de la seconde personne », Revue de métaphysique et de morale, 1954.. Such negative effects may include instrumentalisation for the purposes of reputation, the arrogance that may come from bestowing on beneficiaries assistance they are unable to return, or a lack of recognition from third party actors who may refuse that assistance categorically (which would mean necessarily accepting their refusal).
Let us look at the case of Rwanda as an example of this third phenomenon. Attempts at reconciling with the memory of the Rwandan genocide are present in political discourses and in public policy. They establish a connection between national cohesion (attachment to a country scarred by the past) and personal resilience (healing by surpassing one’s own limits), a dynamic supported by NGOs involved in this cathartic project to break away from hatred. But benevolence is misguided when it imposes a duty for forgiveness on victims who are not yet open to excuses. It ‘smothers indignation(5)Valérie Rosoux, « Rwanda : la réconciliation idéalisée », Déviance et société, 2016for some of these victims, and also lacks subtlety in its consideration of them according to a single homogenous profile. In other words, forgiveness entrepreneurs are mistaken in the validity of their own position. An enlightened vision of benevolence accepts these darker sides. It cannot erase them by attempting to impose benevolence. Without necessary steps, such an attempt could derail into the world described by Stanislav Lem at the heart of his book The Futurological Congress, a world in which a totalitarian-leaning government alters citizens’ behaviour by releasing bombs of mutual benevolence.
F.R.: Ramel: Taking benevolence into account in foreign policy is not necessarily new. Jacqueline de Romilly described this in her excellent book dedicated to gentleness in Greek thought(6)Jacqueline de Romilly, La douceur dans la pensée grecque, Les Belles Lettres, 1978.as did Robert Axelrod in his famous theory on cooperative behaviour (avoiding unnecessary conflicts when the other cooperates, being open if once partner prioritises an end to cooperation and being forgiving after responding to a provocation, being transparent to encourage adaptation from other players). Beyond these classical references, foreign policy based on benevolence implies a certain temperance or strategic restraint. It supposes subscribing to the harm principle through exemplarity as a way of reinforcing the principle of due diligence based on the idea that ‘he who can intervene to prevent harm, but does nothing, is equally guilty’. Foreign policy based on benevolence can be seen in armed conflicts, environmental protection, or human rights. It supposes that reciprocal vulnerabilities are taken into account in the context of transnational issues that expose all societies to the same risks (pandemics or climate change for example). However, these implications remain partly subject to several processes. I will only present two of them here: not succumbing to strategic excesses; and benefiting from full and entire recognition as a state, beyond the legal dimension.
Major powers adopt positions that are liable to succumb to the difficulties of the former and the weaknesses of the latter. Allow me to quote Pierre Hassner again. He compared the foreign policy restraint of Switzerland to that of Russia, invested with a civilising mission against Europe perceived as decadent. The line between ‘respecting differences and affirming superiority’ is a delicate one, according to him. This difficult balance sometimes provokes resentment, such as in the Russian case after the Cold War. The diplomatic marginalisation of Moscow, associated with the increasingly salient influence of the West in the post-Soviet space as well as a general support for democratic values pushed Putin to take measures aiming to revive a waning identity (the annexing of Crimea, Russian military offensives in Ukraine, etc.). In other words, foreign policy based on benevolence seems a delicate business, but it can by no means be confused with military intervention for the purposes of transforming political regimes – as illustrated by the Libyan case – even though detractors of benevolence often use this example to deny its existence in the global space.
F.R.: These two approaches are particularly stimulating. The first reveals the mechanisms of domination and the second emphasises altruistic behaviour in support of the most vulnerable. I have chosen to not follow either for two reasons. The first stems from my attachment to the sociology of international relations. Although I quote Foucault in the introduction, in order to shed light on benevolence as potential, echoing the idea of moral perfectionism, I am drawing more on What is Enlightenment? than on Discipline and Punish. In other words, I do not exclude the dark sides of benevolence as an instrument of domination, but nor do I make this the guiding line of my demonstration. This does not prevent the possibility of future collaboration because during a conversation with Didier Bigo on this theme, points of convergence appeared, such as the exploration of conditions (social as well as biological) that explain why a terrorist actor may not take action (thus strategic restraint). As for the second approach, ferocious criticism such as that by Yves Michaud has reduced the philosophy of benevolence to care theory. Yet the first is much broader than the second, although both are built from the same foundation of solicitude. On the one hand, the philosophy of benevolence is based on a conception of humanity that goes beyond vulnerability, and on the other it is not limited to a politics of compassion.
F.R. : Philosopher and sociologist Georg Simmel emphasised the close correlation between the development of individuality and the broadening of social ties. For him, ‘that individuality of being and doing increases in general to the extent that the social circle surrounding the individual expands(7)Georg Simmel, Sociologie. Études sur les formes de socialisation, PUF, 1999..In other words, there is a search for universality that operates through the recognition of singularity both individuals (moving from quantitative individualism to qualitative individualism in the evolution of modernity) and of groups. Paul Ricoeur, a major philosopher of solicitude and hospitality, developed an understanding of universalism that was more in keeping with this perpetually renewed search for recognition. One difficulty appears, however, when we seek to extend benevolence beyond immediate circles because the more action is directed at far away strangers the more benevolence loses intensity. Moreover, it is impossible to maintain benevolence towards everyone all the time. There must be a degree of selectivity. Indeed, as the philosopher Robert Spaermann emphasises, ‘The receivers of benevolence are so numerous that we cannot possible come to the aid of each in the same way.(8)Robert Spaemann, Bonheur et bienveillance. Essai sur l’éthique, PUF, 1997..
F.R.: One aspect of my research in recent decades is somewhat unusual. It explores sensitivity in the global space using images and as you have said music, whether pop music or high culture. But there is something else in this book it is important to remember – the subtitle. This is a political essay. In other words, I propose an exploration. I invite readers to lift certain veils, to embark upon an adventure. This leads to a freedom of tone that I had not yet experimented with, a style and form that a different from my previous texts. Moreover, the artistic elements are materials that allow us to shed light on political and social reality in less abrupt ways. Drawing on the work of Emeric Lhuisset on global warming or lockdowns (‘The Sound of Silence’), or by Saype on cooperation between cities (‘Beyond Walls’), or more broadly on paintings from Holbein to Lévy-Dhurmer, I have tried to depict benevolence as attention to the other and the natural milieu, based on artistic representations. I am not the first to take this path at Sciences Po. Bruno Latour with the school of political arts, and of course, Laurence Bertrand-Dorléac, the current president of the FNSP, are pioneers in this area. I have modestly set out to follow in their footsteps.
To conclude, can you say a few words about the very beautiful map chosen to illustrate the cover of the book?
F.R.:This magnificent map was first shown to me by a friend, who is a CNRS researcher in medieval history. It is the work of Oronce Fine (1494–1555) who was the first chair of mathematics at the Collège de France and the cartographer of King François I. It is inspired by the cordiform map projections (heart-shaped) invented by the German Johannes Werner in the early 16th century. Although it is approximative due to the partial knowledge of the era (the connection between North America and Asia for example), it provides the first account of the southern lands not yet explored. Evidently, it has an undeniable symbolic weight that resonates with the spirit of the book. One the one hand, bearing in mind the imagination as a human faculty that according to Bachelard ‘creates a higher reality’, and on the other evoking an attachment to the Earth, because to quote Zygmunt Bauman, at the end of his Retrotopia (2017) ‘we – human inhabitants of Earth – are in the either/or situation: we face either joining hands, or common graves.’
Interview by Miriam Périer, translation by Katharine Throssell.
Frédéric Ramel is a university professor, member of the Center for International Studies (CERI) and director of the Political Science Department. His work focuses on security issues, diplomacy and international organizations. It also decenters the gaze by exploring little treated objects such as the role of music and more broadly acoustics in the global space.
More about the book
Presentation of the book in the media
Further reading
—Hutcheson F., Hutcheson, Francis. 1755. A System of Moral Philosophy. Selection reprinted in British moralists, ed. L. A. Selby-Bigge. 1964. 419–425. Indianapolis : Bobbs-Merrill.
– Jullien F., Fonder la morale. Dialogue de Mencius avec un philosophe des Lumières, Paris, Grasset, 1995.
– Singer P., L’altérité efficace, Paris, Les Arènes, 2018.
– Van Cauwelaert D., La bienveillance est une arme absolue, Paris, Editions de l’Observatoire, 2019.
Notes[+]
↑1 | An acoustic reading refers to the role of listening, silence, and resonance in the everyday work of diplomats who produce sound, modulate their voices, organise concerts as instruments of representation and mediation. See Damien Mahiet, Rebekah Ahrendt, Frédéric Ramel. “Diplomacy: Audible and Resonant,” Diplomatica. A Journal of Diplomacy and Society, Dec. 2021 |
---|---|
↑2 | « Interview with Rodrigo Tavares over Paradiplomatic Trend », IR Insider, 17 septembre 2018. |
↑3 | Andrew Linklater, The Problem of Harm in World Politics, Cambridge University Press, 2011. Andrew Linklater, Violence and Civilization in the Western States-Systems, Cambridge University Press, 2016. |
↑4 | Paul Ricœur, « Sympathie et respect : phénoménologie et éthique de la seconde personne », Revue de métaphysique et de morale, 1954. |
↑5 | Valérie Rosoux, « Rwanda : la réconciliation idéalisée », Déviance et société, 2016 |
↑6 | Jacqueline de Romilly, La douceur dans la pensée grecque, Les Belles Lettres, 1978. |
↑7 | Georg Simmel, Sociologie. Études sur les formes de socialisation, PUF, 1999. |
↑8 | Robert Spaemann, Bonheur et bienveillance. Essai sur l’éthique, PUF, 1997. |